In one of the great statements against human naturalism,
G.K. Chesterton argued that, “We can accept [man] as an animal, if we can live
with a fabulous animal.”
This is quite an arresting image. It turns our traditional
version of the fable upside down. And yet this tergiversation is obviously valid.
Instead of the animal that talks, tells stories, laughs about the past or
dreams about the future, we see human beings doing the same thing. And of course,
this is fabulous, because animals (which supposedly include us) don’t do such
things.
It is also a ringing challenge to those who deny human
exceptionalism. And most captivating of all is that wonderful word “fabulous”. I
say wonderful because in addition to the traditional sense of that word (of
talking and thinking in ways that fabulous animals do - and in ways that
non-fabulous animals do not) we are also fabulous because we can willfully
transcend our mortal nature. We are also wonderful. Indeed, we are fabulous.
One of my favorite fables is Aesop’s fable of The Dog and
the Wolf. In the story, a hungry and skinny wolf meets a fat and happy dog. The
wolf asks the dog how he seems to be so well off. The dog replies that his
master feeds him for watching the house at night and for keeping thieves away.
And then the wolf notices the scar around the dog’s neck. He learns that the
scar is from the rope that keeps the dog tied up during the day, and the wolf
decides to leave. “Well,” says the wolf as he departs, “you can just keep your
nice, fat happiness, I’ll take my skinny old freedom any day or night. I’d
rather be free than fat.”
Chesterton asks us to consider why a talking and reasoning
human being is no more remarkable than a talking or reasoning wolf. This is so
obvious – or at least it should be – that we marvel at the institutional
sophistry that ignores it.
Suppose for the sake of argument, however, that humans are
no more remarkable than any other living species. This means, of course, that we
inherited our likes and dislikes, our hopes and fears, and our many biological
constraints from other forms of life.
This also means that even our most inspiring moral
achievements: The Decalogue, Magna Carta, The Sermon on the Mount, etc., were
only ways to enhance the reproductive success of their respective authors. It
means that we are really only interested, one by one, in taking care of our own
carnal self. We are forced by our biological history to be individualists.
Perhaps you don’t like the portrayal of this word
“individualism” in such a negative way. Especially if you are a warm-blooded
American, you believe that individualism is one of the great virtues of your
heritage. I know that I most certainly do.
But the word “individualism” didn’t start out this way.
Yehoshua Arieli has pointed out that the concept is of non-American origin and
that it represented an ideology in direct opposition to our current system of
values. To be an individualist meant to have an excessive regard to personal
interests. In a word, to be selfish, even to the nth degree. It was
individualism, for example, that was responsible for the abuses of the French
Revolution. And it is individualism that is the enemy of our higher religious
sensibilities.
Of course it is also individualism that lies at the heart of
Darwinian naturalism. Each individual is inherently programmed to look after
itself. Survival of the fittest is the epigram inscribed over the lintels of
our modern institutions.
But in America we changed that meaning. After all, our
ancestors came to this land with a personal optimism and dreamed of success.
Some of them failed. But many of them didn’t. And through the years we have
adopted a can-do attitude that not only recognizes magnanimous behavior, but
has come to expect it.
It is the individual, after all, that takes out the
neighbor’s trash when she is on vacation. It is the individual that helps a
handicapped stranger cross the street. It is the individual that decides, even
in the middle of a hard day, to follow the admonitions of Christ.
Our greatest examples of human excellence are generally
religious individuals. And we recognize their excellence in direct proportion
to their examples of serving others. As Robert Bellah has pointed out, a
prophet is never a private individual. Any truthful assessment of human nature
must deal with these remarkable individuals just as they must deal with the
egotist. It should be clear that individualism can be a lot of different
things.
Individualism, like the wolf in Aesop’s fable, insists on
personal autonomy. Unlike the dog that is tethered to its master’s decisions,
the individualist decides to either follow a carnal nature or to follow a
higher law. In a very real way, our individual response to the world determines
what kind of fabulous animal we will be. We can remain guttered in the mortal
nature “red in tooth and claw” or we can overcome our carnal instincts and live
a remarkable life. Only as individuals can we decide to live a life that
transcends our individual selfishness. Only as individuals can we decide to be
charitable – or, to use the proper academic word, can we decide to be
altruistic.
The altruist is the humanitarian that helps others when the
offered help provides no benefit to himself. The altruist might be a young man
who helps others to escape from a fire. It might be a women volunteering at a
homeless shelter. Any non-reciprocal aid to a non-relative falls into this
category of altruism. Needless to say, many human naturalists deny that any
such thing exists. To them, any apparent altruistic act is merely a hidden
attempt at winning favors. One wonders what sort of human beings these
theorists think we are.
(In fairness, though, there has not been enough thought
given to these two forms of altruism. I mean the spontaneous help given to a
stranger (the type focused on by evolutionary theorists – perhaps because it is
amenable to their theories) and the thoughtful transcendence of self that a
determined religious commitment develops.)
There has been a great deal of academic posturing around
this concept of altruism. This is because a great deal is at stake. On the
surface, and for all practical reasons, charitable acts to others (especially to
non-relatives) do not make Darwinian sense. And if this is true, then a great
deal of the humanist argument fails.
It is a measure of our myopia that we even fall for these
naturalistic arguments. The very reality of our individuality confronts us on
every side, every day, and with everyone we meet. The denial of this
individuality is no longer tenable. The biological laws of meiotic recombination
make it so.
And yet this same ineluctable individuality forces us to
acknowledge that we are very different from the rest of the created order. Our
individualism greatly transcends a mere genetic reshuffling. It involves the
will and our mental and spiritual awareness. And herein lies the great irony: that
our institutional naturalism denies our fabulous nature even as our natural individualism
insists upon it.
So next time you stop to talk to your dog, or to rub the
sore around its neck, remember our friend G. K. Chesterton, and consider just
what it all means. I think you will agree with us. We truly are fabulous.
References
Chesterton’s statement comes from The Everlasting Man (the last paragraph of Chapter I, The Man in
the Cave). My copy of The Dog and the Wolf is on page 17 of Aesop’s Fables, published by Easton
Press, 1979. My summary of Arieli’s work on individualism comes from Gary Wills’s
book Head and Heart, American
Christianities, published by The Penguin Press in 2007. Robert Bellah’s
point about prophets is on page 317 of Religion
in Human Evolution (published by The Belknap Press in 2011).
No comments:
Post a Comment